2023-10-08

381: Categories Equivalence Is Equivalence Relation

<The previous article in this series | The table of contents of this series | The next article in this series>

A description/proof of that categories equivalence is equivalence relation

Topics


About: category

The table of contents of this article


Starting Context



Target Context


  • The reader will have a description and a proof of the proposition that equivalence of categories is an equivalence relation.

Orientation


There is a list of definitions discussed so far in this site.

There is a list of propositions discussed so far in this site.


Main Body


1: Description


Equivalence of categories is an equivalence relation.


2: Proof


Let C1,C2,C3 be any categories such that C1 is equivalent with C2 and C2 is equivalent with C3.

Let us check the reflexivity. Is C1 equivalent with C1? Let us take the functors, F1,1:C1C1 and F1,1:C1C1, which means that same F1,1 is for the both directions, that are the identity functor, 1C1. Is there a natural isomorphism between F1,1F1,1 and 1C1? F1,1F1,1=1C1. For the natural transformations, η:1C11C1 and θ:1C11C1, let us take the identity natural transformation, 11C1. θη=11C111C1=11C1=11C111C1=ηθ. So, η is a natural isomorphism.

Let us check the symmetry. Is C2 equivalent with C1? There are some functors, F1,2:C1C2 and F2,1:C2C1, such that F2,1F1,21C1 and F1,2F2,11C2. So, there are the functors, F2,1:C2C1 and F1,2:C1C2, such that F1,2F2,11C2 and F2,1F1,21C1.

Let us check the transitivity. Is C1 equivalent with C3? There are F1,2:C1C2 and F2,1:C2C1 such that F2,1F1,21C1 with some natural isomorphisms, η1,2:F2,1F1,21C1,θ1,2:1C1F2,1F1,2, and F1,2F2,11C2 with some natural isomorphisms, η2,1:F1,2F2,11C2,θ2,1:1C2F1,2F2,1. There are F2,3:C2C3 and F3,2:C3C2 such that F3,2F2,31C2 with some natural isomorphisms, η2,3:F3,2F2,31C2,θ2,3:1C2F3,2F2,3, and F2,3F3,21C3 with some natural isomorphisms, η3,2:F2,3F3,21C3,θ3,2:1C3F2,3F3,2.

Let us take F1,3=F2,3F1,2:C1C2C3 and F3,1=F2,1F3,2:C3C2C1.

Is F3,1F1,31C1? Are there some natural transformations, η1,3:F3,1F1,31C1 and θ1,3:1C1F3,1F1,3, such that θ1,3η1,3=1F3,1F1,3 and η1,3θ1,3=11C1? Let us define η1,3,c:=η1,2,cF2,1(η2,3,F1,2(c)), which makes sense because η2,3,F1,2(c):F3,2F2,3(F1,2(c))F1,2(c), F2,1(η2,3,F1,2(c)):F2,1F3,2F2,3(F1,2(c))F2,1F1,2(c), and η1,2,c:F2,1F1,2(c)c while η1,3,c:F3,1F1,3(c)=F2,1F3,2F2,3F1,2(c)c. Is η1,3 really a natural transformation? For any morphism in C1, α:cc, αη1,3,c=η1,3,cF3,1F1,3(α)=η1,3,cF2,1F3,2F2,3F1,2(α)? The left hand side is αη1,2,cF2,1(η2,3,F1,2(c))=η1,2,cF2,1F1,2(α)F2,1(η2,3,F1,2(c))=η1,2,cF2,1(F1,2(α)η2,3,F1,2(c)). The right hand side is η1,2,cF2,1(η2,3,F1,2(c))F2,1F3,2F2,3F1,2(α)=η1,2,cF2,1(η2,3,F1,2(c)F3,2F2,3F1,2(α)). But F1,2(α)η2,3,F1,2(c)=η2,3,F1,2(c)F3,2F2,3F1,2(α), so, the both sides equal, so, η1,3 is a natural transformation. η1,3,c is an isomorphism, because η2,3,F1,2(c) is so, the equivalence functor, F2,1, preserves isomorphism, by the proposition that any equivalence functor preserves and reflects monics, epics, bimorphisms, split monics, split epics, isomorphisms, and commutative diagrams, and η1,2,c is so. Then, there is the inverse of η1,3,c, η1,3,c1, and θ1,3,c=η1,3,c1. θ1,3 is a natural transformation, because from αη1,3,c=η1,3,cF3,1F1,3(α), θ1,3,cαη1,3,cθ1,3,c=θ1,3,cη1,3,cF3,1F1,3(α)θ1,3,c, θ1,3,cα=F3,1F1,3(α)θ1,3,c.

Is F1,3F3,11C3? Yes: by the symmetry, C3 is equivalent with C2 and C2 is equivalent with C1, and the symmetric argument of the previous paragraph can be used here.


References


<The previous article in this series | The table of contents of this series | The next article in this series>